The Socio-Economic Status of Dual-Roled Women in Canada
Home
Page Title

X

“STALLED REVOLUTION”? FACING THE SOCIO-ECONOMIC STATUS OF CANADIAN WOMEN WITH NEW PARADIGMS OF WELFARE AND LABOUR

GLOBUS term paper

August 26, 2008

The push towards full economic equality for disadvantaged or disenfranchised groups and individuals is obviously of fundamental importance from the point of view of social justice. But before we begin a discussion on our particular topic concerning the socio-economic status of women in Canada, we would first like to contextualize our discussion in relation to “human rights”.

The notion of “human rights” has concrete bases in codes of law, philosophies, and religions which cross cultures throughout history. The recent history of the idea of human rights as universal and inalienable is sourced in Western Enlightenment thought. The Enlightenment saw the birth of “first generation rights” with a demand for equality in a political sense. “Rights” took on a more diverse application with the rise of socialism and a new emphasis on economic and social equality. Experience within the framework of human rights has led to greater insights as to their inseparable interdependencies and interactions with each other.

“JUSTICE” IN RELATION TO SOCIO-ECONOMIC RIGHTS
The wider concern of “justice” is considerably older than that of “human rights” in particular - among philosophers, we see works such as Plato’s Republic, which entire work is constructed around the single question of the nature of justice, and we find a classical definition of justice in Aristotle’s Ethics, that of “giving to each one his due.” A fundamental difference in context and emphasis may be seen in the discussion surrounding “justice” and the discussion surrounding “rights” - rights seem to ensure that at the particular level of individual or identifiable groups, that not one is sacrificed or forgotten for the sake of ‘other’ interests and seem generally to be discovered in the context of their having been abused - a justice-based approach tends to be linked with generic problems or a more communitarian approach. Though the words differ in their contexts, one might say that essentially justice and rights are the Though the words differ in their contexts, one might say that essentially justice and rights are the same thing and imply one another for their mutual realization - just as the individual exists because of the community and the community is based upon the individual. Justice presupposes the interconnection of political, social, and economic structures which makes it possible for the capacities or rights of all individuals to be maximally realized in accordance with their right to self-determination. When Kant formulated his categorical imperative for moral action, the basis for treating human beings is always to treat each as ‘an end in himself(herself)’. This fundamental principle of being an end in oneself confers the possibility of possessing rights. This “being an end in oneself” further implies that there are conscious and voluntary or moral capacities at stake, because something receives the status of being an end in itself when it has the capacity of proposing or claiming purpose. Another way of putting the basis of rights is “the right to have rights”.

INSTITUTING RIGHTS - RECREATING STRUCTURES

“It is quite possible that at a particular point in time or in a given state of affairs a right is not feasible to be realized unless appropriate changes in the institutions and social arrangements are introduced (…) changing the institutions or (…) institutionalizing the right, would be a part of the obligation of the duty-bearers.”

The advantage of the language of “rights” stemming from our particular legal and liberal humanistic culture are immediately evident - theoretically, a legal basis indicates unconditionality and universality; the possibility of enforcement via legal and social mechanisms; and a public text, covenant, or some other equivalent to which plaintiffs can appeal and which provide ground for interpretation and progress at the academic and practical levels. However, formulating laws is not always sufficient, particularly in the case of economic, social, and cultural rights (or to import a more recent term originating from “developing” countries - “development” rights). Rights can precede their concrete and binding formulation in law. While laws can be agents of social change, on the other hand it must be recognized that the law cannot (or at least does not) contain all possible forms of justice, nor, even where laws contain essential principles, do they always provide clear recommendations for their implementation, especially as developmental rights as we experience their requirements, are essentially open-ended, calling for constant review. One must comprehend the underlying social, cultural, and sub-cultural causes of inequality and proffer solutions sensitive to their contours. Human rights law (and quasi-law) continue to serve a regulative role even these theorizations, as a reminder in the attempts to pursue “justice” that particular groups or individuals cannot be sacrificed or overlooked, thus ensuring the real cultivation of human “flourishing.“ It is necessary for the striving of groups, the theorizing of academics, the innovative experiments of political or intra-political bodies, and the hard work of experts in economics and other fields to bring new configurations of justice into our conceptual and experiential horizons. This is the reason I have chosen, instead of analyzing past achievements, to structure my essay, first, to pointing out the sources of the inequities of the current situation, and secondly and more briefly, to propose new paradigms in light of the unique factors in this inequality.

This essay is engaged within our own specific context of Canada. Our concern is the economic disparity between men and women, particularly manifested in the gender wage gap.

CANADA’S GENDER WAGE GAP

In view of the fact that many laudable efforts towards achieving equality rights for women have taken place over the past century (as well as many accompanying changes at the level of cultural consciousnesses) many Canadians were surprised to discover the fact that women in Canada are still earning less than three quarters of men’s wages. In 2005 (the most recent year for figures), women working full-time for the full year earned an average of $39,200, or 70.5% as much as comparable men who earned an average of $55,700.

The natural response to this state of affairs is to have recourse to rights-based legal mechanisms. It has been necessary (and it is a continual effort) to address “systemic” and “intentional” discrimination within the workplace which formed a harsh reality in much of our recent history. For a brief overview of the successes as well as of the challenges that continue to face pay equity, please see Gender Equality in the Labour Market.

Efforts toward a “fair playing-ground” in the form of anti-discrimination laws and policies are as we have noted, necessary. However, achieving real justice, as we have hinted, requires not only fair playing fields, but a recognition on our part that people bring different burdens to the playing field. Gender difference poses a particularly challenging problem in this respect, in view of the “roles” that have accrued not only by exterior political impositions but which have also become deeply ingrained in other discourses, whether religious, philosophical, or even scientific or biological - to such an extent as to affect women’s internal identities and consequently their expectations for themselves, their capacities, and their “deserts”. A theory of “self-expectation” stemming from a “scripted” gender role in Canadian women has not been specifically explored as a cause of the gender gap - in a way, it seems partially discounted by the alacrity with which women have entered the workforce in such vast numbers. One cannot help asking the question why men have not adequately increased their participation in the unpaid labour force, which may be a fruitful line of inquiry that has remained largely unexplored. This is particularly odd given that male involvement in child care holds tremendous implications for women’s overall status.

CAREGIVING - WOMEN’S “HIDDEN” BURDEN

“Women, regardless of their labour market status, continue to bear the primary responsibilities for dependent care and household work in all industrialized countries.”

Gender Equality and the Labour Market - Lessons Learned

“From the standpoint of time, married women, particularly those with children, continue to do significantly more housework than married men….” Converging Gender Roles

Mothers, regardless of employment status, consistently feel more time-crunched than fathers (Zukewich 2003 finding, cited in Converging Gender Roles)

For generations in Canada, women’s unpaid care giving was not accorded the status of labour. The significant contribution that women provide via their care giving and domestic work is a fairly recent “discovery”.

WOMEN’S REVOLUTION; MEN’S “STALLED REVOLUTION”?

Women have entered the workforce in vast numbers in the past couple of decades. There are many reasons for this surge - a change in culture, extensive anti-discrimination laws and the opening of many occupations that were traditionally closed, the seizing of opportunities for greater education. While women have entered the workforce in burgeoning numbers, it appears that they have shed little of their care giving responsibilities, perhaps because men for their part have not come to equal women in stepping beyond gendered roles by filling the remaining quota of care giving labour.

In 1986, women with children did 2.2 more hours of unpaid labour per day than their male counterparts (3.3 versus 1.1 hours). The difference has since decreased to 1.3 hours in 2005 (2.8 versus 1.5 hours), which is still a substantial disparity.

Something that is also important to note is the difference in kind that often takes place between male and female unpaid labour.

Despite the fact that women are, overall, healthier and happier when they participate in paid labour, they still carry heavy pressures because of their “double day“. When women are co-earners with male spouses, two thirds of the women felt time-stressed compared with one-half of the men. When members of a dual-earner relationship work full-time and there are children, women tend to report dissatisfaction with the balance between life and work (only 52% of women with children in couples with long hours felt satisfied with their work/life balance or WLB, the lowest rate overall in the study, in contrast with 71% of their male counterparts).

UNPAID LABOUR: ECONOMIC COSTS FOR WOMEN

Being the primary caregivers of children continues to be reflected in women's lower incomes, even with their increased labour force participation.”

What stands out in these findings is that women bear their care giving responsibilities in a way that is different than men, which, we will see, considerably impedes their opportunities for economic equality within a market-driven labour force. The incapacity of the labor market to integrate caregivers with divided responsibilities may perhaps also be inferred from the fact that, even in relationships where the male and female partners formerly shared fairly equal divisions of unpaid and paid labor, that parenthood is the occasion of a trend toward traditional gendered divisions of labour.

The effect of a woman’s commitment to care giving is that she seeks a job that can be subordinated to this priority. Women are over-represented in non-standard jobs in fact, in 1999 these jobs accounted for 41% of female employment (while only 29% of male employment). The problems with non-standard jobs, particularly with the kind of low-skilled, service jobs in which women tend to be over-represented, is that they provide smaller and less stable incomes; they tend to lack medical benefits; and can be stagnant or unrewarding from the viewpoint of human interest. Even when care giving women work full-time, standard positions, they tend to work fewer hours, and they are often excluded from consideration for raises and career advancement because their presence at their job is punctuated by short and long absences, whether for maternity leaves or for family emergencies.

Naturally, women are at a still greater risk for economic instability without the support of a co-earning spouse. There are many more single mothers than single fathers: “In 1961, only 9% of all families with children were headed by a female lone-parent, numbers that increased to 16.4% in 1991 and 20.1% in 2001, rates that are much higher than among men. In a world where one family breadwinner is rarely sufficient to stay economically afloat, women who face the full responsibility for financial as well as care giving responsibilities face crushing and sometimes impossible burdens. It is no wonder then that women form the majority of the poor in Canada and that mothering is the single most important factor leading to poverty in old age.

POLICY PROPOSALS

The final part of this essay concerns strategies for remedying these problems in light of our preceding discussions. In proposing areas for policy reform, the report Gender Equality in the Labour Market: Lessons Learned identifies five areas of reform: employment standards, equal opportunities policies, policies that affect pay, labour market training, and policies to reconcile work ad family responsibilities. We have already partially remarked on the efforts in the field of equal pay for work of equal value although there is much more to be said in that direction (see the report for a more comprehensive approach) The question of labour training is also a very important one. We will focus, however, on more structural reforms with a view to reconciling work and family responsibilities.

Provision of adequate child care would be an fundamental component of any reform in this area. However, daycare in and of itself is not a comprehensive solution. On the one hand, it could possibly send the message that unpaid care-giving labour is economically and socially of low value, which is contrary to human experience and would furthermore fail to give adequate recognition to the long commitment that women have borne to it. However, from a practical point of view, while making daycare available would be of undeniable and obvious benefit for single mothers, and is immediately linked with our objective of increasing a woman’s economic status via increasing her available hours for paid employment, it would not necessarily mean, even in a dual-parent relationship, that a woman would not still carry most of the primary burdens of family coordination (scheduling, etc other stuff) after daycare hours in additions of her workweek. Thus while reliable and affordable or free daycare would increase a woman’s wage earning time, it may not decrease her time-stress significantly.

A more comprehensive solution would include integrating the right to leisure and the choice to give care for women and other workers as well as the right of children to reasonable leisured access to their parents (while keeping in mind the objective of encouraging a better distribution of parental care between the male and female parents). These are the reasons why we have chosen to focus more on structural changes.

There is sufficient evidence to show that the labour force is not adequately accommodating for those who bear parenting or care giving responsibilities, partly because the current configuration of our market-driven labour force continues to assume the traditional model of separate spheres in breadwinning and care giving. If we reformed the labour force as a whole so that it addressed the reality that every earner may carry equal responsibilities as a caregiver, women would no longer be trapped in non-standard jobs, because all jobs, including highly skilled ones, would have already incorporated standards of flexibility.

FLEXIBLE WORK - BENDING PARADIGMS

“(E)xisting Canadian workplace practices and regulatory models remain largely based on an old industrial model and a social pattern of the able-bodied white male principal income earner working for a single employer on a full-time permanent basis.” Addressing Work-Life Balance in Canada

One of the most recent interesting trends in job flexibility has been towards “job-sharing.” Job-sharing is in some ways a familiar phenomenon (for example, family-operated businesses and medical doctors) but the idea of proposing job-sharing as a systematic reform in a post-industrialized world still seems to be a novel one. Very little formal investigation of the social and economic impacts of job-sharing has been conducted. On the other hand, state and provincial governments have been experimenting with it, and private-sector studies have showed that job-sharing shows success in matching the need for work/life balance of employees over the different stages of their life cycle, thus maintaining them in the workforce and au courant with their skills, while increasing their capacity for productivity in comparison with a more stream-lined approach to paid labour.

The particular benefits that job-sharing would offer to our context is that women would be able to maintain their place in desirable jobs even if family responsibilities take high priority in their lives. This would enable women who desire (or are moved to from lack of appropriate support) to invest more time in caregiving at certain intervals in their lives to have the possibility for simultaneously maintaining their skills at the level of their cohort. This would eliminate the cases of highly educated women working at jobs that do not match their potential, and it would be a greater incentive for women to pursue highly specialized training in the first place if they knew that they would be able to employ their skills after giving birth. Because of the kinds of jobs it would open to women, job-sharing would mean an increase in earnings at the per/hour levl as well as the likelihood of included benefits. The human value of their workplace would be enriched as information sharing would increase, and the greater stimulation and pleasure which skilled labour provides would enrich the self-esteem and morale of individual women. Furthermore, success in the workplace is correlated with empowering women to negotiate their labour in the home. If the workplace itself is changed, it would ensure that women would be able to negotiate more help from their male co-parents, who would be similarly enabled to meet care giving demands because the flexibility of their workplace.

This is one way to help to narrow the gender gap. This solution, however, fails to address our concerns on the issue of workers earning sufficient wages to support themselves and their children, for a part-time job would need to be especially well-paid in order to suffice for one’s own needs and one’s children - this is a question that is particularly urgent for single mothers, who do not have a partner to share childcare and earning quotas. What about these women and their children?

SOCIAL WELFARE

The welfare system is often conceptualized as a “social net” for the disenfranchised of society (a category for which single mothers are heavily at risk). There is, in Canada, at the heart of our notion of “welfare” an unusual dissonance with a philosophy of human rights that is otherwise much-touted.

Participation in the fruits of shared resources and the fruits of human advancement should not be considered something that is earned on the basis of approved forms of labour, or to be granted by special favor in other circumstances, but is a basic human right sourced in the stake that each member has in the human community. The Universal Declaration states that in particular motherhood and childhood are entitled to special care and assistance, (CITE) thereby recognizing the unique risks and disadvantages which mothers and their children can face in many current social structures. Economic equality is the fundamental requirement for other rights to be meaningful - it ensures access to the resources necessary to fulfill fundamental material needs and furthermore, for those who are only beginning to gain a place in complex social networks (because of youth or overwhelming responsibilities or other factors), it forms the necessary starting capital for investing in their capacities through education, training, cultural and leisure activities, and other forms of social participation, integration, and networking processes.

Apart from conceptual problems, there are also structural problems with the Canadian welfare system. Essentially, the Canadian welfare system was organized with male earners in mind - to fill in their unemployment gaps. In addition to the inadequacies of a welfare system that does not recognize the contributions, still less the specific needs of mothers and caregivers, there is considerable feeling and stigma against those who are poor in many Anglo-influenced countries. Would-be welfare recipients are subject to a means-based test, and women to invasive checks to ensure there is no “man hiding around the house“, and in general to a humiliating, alienating and wearisome process which, far short of respecting their status as persons and their achievements in attempting to provide for their children, imposes upon them an atmosphere of suspicion. Furthermore, actually receiving the benefit is contingent upon arbitrary, senseless factors such as a “willingness to work“ - and is also subject to bureaucratic discretion. In addition to these problems, the welfare system creates a powerful disincentive to work, as obtaining any kind of paid employment cuts welfare funding, which makes employment undesirable particularly when the kind of jobs (at least to those in demographic seeking welfare who are disadvantaged by care giving responsibilities, lack of education or experience) offer less income and benefits than one would receive under the welfare system.

It has been observed that public policy is especially ambiguous about supporting women in their dual burden, seeming to “waver” between supporting women’s “earning role” and “caring role” while providing sufficient support to neither, with the result that women are abandoned to poverty in both of their capacities.

BASIC INCOME AND HUMAN RIGHTS

An alternative system to most existing welfare paradigms is making its way in academic circles - namely, a proposal for a basic income that is universal, that is, offered to every citizen, and unconditional, that is, free of a means test or other conditions.

Before we investigate a universal basic income proposal, it would be well to consider an intermediate proposal or what is called a participation wage, which would be available for caregivers, volunteers, the disabled, and similar groups of people who are engaged in other forms of contribution that are not generally elsewhere recognized in economic terms. Julieta Elgarte examines this proposal for its potential to benefit women, but she ultimately identifies a number of administrative difficulties with this kind of solution. James Mulvale suggests that a universally offered income would actually be more feasible in attaining equality for women, and furthermore, the reform would address many other social problems for the same price.

The first reaction with which many people face a the general reaction many give is "feasibility" how is it possible to introduce such a widespread and - presumably - costly reform? Van Parijs treats of these questions, showing that it may not be so impracticable as many people initially suppose it to be. The chief difficulties facing an implementation of a universal benefit may, in fact, be ideological ones. The idea that the individual is entitled to a living income rather than having to “earn” it in accepted forms of labour (otherwise being simply “granted” it in exceptional cases) is difficult to take root even in countries that profess devoted adherence to human rights principles. There is a disinclination to perceive an integral connection and mutual dependency between individual and public interests in Canada that is partially manifested in the fact that most of our social reform policies have taken the shape of collective services. Another indication of this broad attitude is that children are often seen as a private concern or even as a consumer choice, a view which has disastrous impacts for children, naturally, but also for the women who undertake their care.

BI FOR WOMEN - A FEMINIST APPRAISAL

Many authors have rightly seen this ability of a UBI to provide income security for homemakers to be a strong reason for advocating the proposal from a gender perspective. Alstott (2001), for instance, stresses that American women face two distinctive economic risks the combination of which translates into lifelong income insecurity, namely main responsibility for child care and low earnings (due in part to women’s adjusting their working lives to accommodate family needs).“

The benefits that a basic income would have for the caregivers with whom we are concerned are fairly obvious - it means a sure, steady income to provide for themselves and for their children (similar to Baby Bonus - check).

The implications of this would mean that (assuming concomitant reforms in childcare) a woman would be more free to pursue a career simultaneously with her care giving responsibilities if she so desired, while not leaving her impoverished if she chooses to dedicate her full time to care giving. It would also give a care giving woman exit power from relationships in which she did not previously have, in light of the fact that she depended upon a co-earner (or even sole breadwinner in some cases) to provide for her children. Furthermore, with this increased power, women would be capable of negotiating different aspects of a relationship - including, but not restricted to, equitable divisions of labour. Finally, Basic Income would provide women with security for retirement, regardless of their paid work hours.

CRITICISM

There is also a cogent criticism of Basic Income from the gender perspective. Jim Mulvale cites the concerns of Ingrid Robeyns in this regard, that BI could re-entrench traditional gender roles and mean an actual loss in income if BI benefits are less than job incomes, as well as the loss of social rewards of paid labor participation. This may in turn create further problems such as statistical discrimination against women. Robeyns, however, treats this concern by recommending that a BI shold be supplemented “with other social policy measures that liberate women (and at the same time men) from gender role expectations.” One such “social policy measure” could be the implementation of our recommendation of job-sharing as a new labour norm along with a mandatory shorter workweek which, with the accompanying cultural changes, would accommodate women, encourage the unpaid labour participation of men, and thus prevent the reforging of traditional gender roles and hierarchy. If BI and labour reform were implemented together, BI would on the one hand subsidize the shorter workweek, while labour reform on the other hand would ensure that the paid labour market remains both feasible, attractive, and accommodating to care giving women. This labour reform would empower women by enabling them to keep all the human advantages of rewarding labour outside of intensive care giving, giving them both power and skills to negotiate with their male partners, while at the same time instantiating a permanent and explicit space to further expedite the male crossing of the gendered work barriers.

CONCLUSION

Achieving economic equality for women in Canada is a complicated issue that requires cognizance of the concrete impediments that women face in the current economic and labor structures because of their continuing care giving responsibilities, the lack of adequate male support, as well as the outdated labour and welfare structures. Much work is to be done in discerning ways to implement structures that are more conducive to producing equity. It would perhaps also be advantageous to bring in more interdisciplinary approaches to balancing the opportunities gap that persists between the sexes - to be attentive to the interwoven histories, both external and internalized, that continue to play an important role in women’s offering themselves in care giving. There also needs to be work done in the exploration and development of the rights of children (and other persons requiring intensive care) and how to achieve these needs from more the concerted standpoints of different disciplines. I hope that this analysis and proposal for structural change will provide an occasion for fruitful reflection and involvement in these matters.

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Ackerman, Bruce, et al. Redesigning distribution: basic income and stakeholder grants as alternative cornerstones for a more egalitarian capitalism. Ed. Erik O. Wright. London ; New York: Verso, 2006.

Andreassen, Bard and Stephen P. Marks, (eds). Development as a Human Right - Legal, Political, and Economic Dimensions. London, England: Harvard University Press, 2006.

Crittenden, Jack. Beyond Individualism: Reconstituting the Liberal Self. New York, Oxford University Press, 1992.

Doucet, Andrea. Do men mother? Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2006.

Drolet, Marie, and Analytical Studies Branch. Wives, Mothers, and Wages: Does Timing Matter? May 01 2002. Statistics Canada. 26 August 2008 <http://www.statcan.ca/english/research/11F0019MIE/11F0019MIE2002186.pdf>.

Elgarte, Julieta. Good for women? Advantages and risks of a basic income from a gender perspective. (Paper given at the XI Bien Congress, University of Cape Town, November 2-4, 2006.) BIEN 26 August 2008 <http://www.epri.org.za/JulietaElgartefullpaper.pdf>

Expert Panel on Accountabilty for Mechanisms for Gender. Equality for women, Beyond the Illusion. 2005. 26 August 2008 <http://www.swc-cfc.gc.ca/resources/panel/report/report_e.pdf>.

Freiler, Christa, et al. Mothers as Earners, Mothers as Carers: Responsibility for Children, Social Policy and the Tax System. Status of Women Canada, 2001. 26 August 2008 <http://www.swc-cfc.gc.ca/pubs/pubspr/0662655206/200103_0662655206_e.pdf>

Friedan, Betty. Beyond Gender: The New Politics of Work and Family. Ed. Brigid O'Farrell. Washington, DC: Woodrow Wilson Center Press, 1997.

Human Resources and Social Development Canada. Work, Family, and Community: Key Issues and Directions for Future Research. HRSDC. 1999. 26 August 2008 <http://www.rhdsc.gc.ca/en/lp/spila/wlb/wfc/02table_of_contents.shtml>.

Human Resources and Social Development Canada. Addressing Work-Life Balance in Canada. HRSDC. 26 August 2008 <http://www1.servicecanada.gc.ca/en/lp/spila/wlb/awlbc/01table_of_contents.shtml>

Human Resources and Social Development Canada. Work-Related Child Care Centres in Canada. 2001. HRSDC. 26 August 2008 <http://www1.servicecanada.gc.ca/en/lp/spila/wlb/wrccc/01presentation.shtml>

Human Resources Development Canada. Gender Equality in the Labour Market. HRDC, 2002. 26 August 2008 <http://www.hrsdc.gc.ca/en/cs/sp/hrsdc/edd/reports/2002-002440/spah14910_e.pdf>.

Ishay, Micheline. The history of Human Rights: from Ancient Times to the Globalization Era. Berkeley: University of California Press, 2004.

Ishay, Micheline (ed). The Human Rights Reader: Major Political Essays, Speeches, and Documents from the Bible to the Present. New York, Routledge, 1997.

Jacobsen, Joyce P. The Economics of Gender. Malden: Blackwell Publishing, 2007.

Marshall, Katherine. "Converging Gender Roles." Perspectives on Labour and Income. 7.7 (July 2006). Statistics Canada. 26 August 2008 <http://www.statcan.ca/english/freepub/75-001-XIE/10706/art-1.htm>.

Melden, A. I. Human Rights. Belmont, California: Wadsworth Publishing Company, Inc., 1970.

Mill, John S. On Liberty and The Subjection of Women, Penguin, New York, 2006 (original essay On the Subjection of Women published 1869).

Mulvale, James P. “Basic Income and the Canadian Welfare State: Exploring the Realms of Possibility.” Basic Income Studies, 3.1 (April 2008). 26 August 2008 <http://www.bepress.com/bis/vol3/iss1/art6/>

Nussbaum, Martha. Women and Human Development. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2000.

Nussbaum, Martha and Glover, Jonathan (eds) Women, Culture, and Development: A Study of Human Capabilities. Oxford, Oxford University Press 1995

Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights. (Joint project by UNESCO and International Institute of Philosophy) France: UNESCO, 1986.

Reichert, Elisabeth. "Human Rights: An Examination of Universalism and Cultural Relativism." Journal of Comparative Social Welfare. 22.1 (April 2006): 23-36.

Robeyns, Ingrid. “An income of one’s own: a radical proposal for welfare state reform in Europe and beyond” in Gender and Development, 2001, 9, 1, pp. 82-89.

Robeyns, Ingrid. “Free Money for All” (book review of Redesigning Distribution. Basic Income and Stakeholder Grants as Cornerstones for an Egalitarian Capitalism edit, E. Olin Wright) The Political Quarterly, 2006, 77 (4), pp. 507-508.

Robeyns, Ingrid. “Reforming the Welfare State: The Case for Basic Income” in Christine Koggel (ed) Moral Issues in Global Perspective, 2006, 2nd edition, pp. 341-348.

Robeyns, Ingrid. Will a Basic Income do Justice to Women? in Analyse und Kritik, 2001, 23. 1, pp. 88-105.

Status of Women Canada. Gender Equality Consultation: Assessing Gender Equality. Status of Women Canada. 26 August 2008 <http://www.swc-cfc.gc.ca/resources/consultations/ges09-2005/assessing_e.html>

Townson, Monica. Poverty Issues for Canadian Women. (August 2005) Status of Women Canada. 26 August 2008 <http://www.swc-cfc.gc.ca/resources/consultations/ges09-2005/poverty_e.pdf>

Townson, Monica. Women in Non-Standard Jobs: The Public Policy Challenge (March 2003) Status of Women Canada. 26 August 2008 <http://www.swc-cfc.gc.ca/pubs/pubspr/0662334809/200303_0662334809_e.pdf>

Zhang, Xuelin, and Analytical Studies Branch. The Post-Childbirth Employment of Canadian Mothers and the Earnings Trajectories of their Continuously Employed Counterparts, 1983 to 2004. August 27 2008. Statistics Canada. 26 August 2008 The results of this study were not yet released by the time I completed this essay; however, it can be accessed after August 27 from this source: <http://www.statcan.ca/bsolc/english/bsolc?catno=11F0019M&CHROPG=1>.

Zhang, Xuelin. "Returning to the Job after Childbirth." Perspectives on Labour and Income. 8.12 (December 2007). Statistics Canada. 26 August 2008 <http://www.statcan.ca/english/freepub/75-001-XIE/2007112/articles/10467-en.pdf>.

FOOTNOTES

This is an oversimplification of the history which, however, will suffice for our purposes. For a more adequate and historical approach, see Ishay’s A History of Human Rights and for texts supporting human rights from biblical scripture to the present, see Ishay’s The Human Rights Reader.

# The success of the cry for “liberty, equality, and fraternity” of the Enlightenment in its own time and even among its own proponents, is subject to much criticism considering both its practical and conceptual failures. (Cf. Ishay, p. 8)

# This is not the last of the “generations” of rights - as of today, we identify three major fields or “generations” of rights corresponding to historical consciousness of them, and all of which are alluded to in the Universal Declaration. The first generation corresponds to civil liberties and other liberal rights, the second, to political, social and economic rights, the third, to communal and national solidarity. (Cf. Ishay, pp. 3-4)

Cite Nicomachean Ethics. While Aristotle is not often directly recognized in the genealogy of human rights, philosophers like Martha Nussbaum will find the “contextual” approach which Aristotle takes to justice to be of peculiar value in in efforts at achieving first and second generation. "Aristotle's insistence on the ethical importance of a vivid perception of concrete circumstances had its own contribution to make (...) to a field that is frequently so preoccupied with formal modeling and abstract theorizing that it fails to come to grips with the daily reality of poor people's lives. (p. xv Introduction, Womand And Human Development)

# For an example of the use of a Kantian justification of rights, see Prologomena to a Study of Human Rights, Vittorio Mathieu (p. 36, subset 19) in Philosophical Foundations for Human Rights

# This formulation is generally attributed to Hannah Arendt.

Arjun Sengupta, The Human Right to Development, pp. 22-23 of Development as a Human Right.

# For more information on the benefits of a rights-based approach, see Jakob K. Hansen and Hans-Otto Sano, The Implications and Value Added of a Rights-Based Approach, pp. 36-56 of Development as a Human Right.

# For a discussion on rights being both the “parents” and the “children” of law, as well a discussion on “feasibility” in relation to “rights” please see Amartya Sen’s Human Rights and Development, p. 1-8 of Development as a Human Right.

The notion of “flourishing”, made most familiar by Martha Nussbaum, indicates a human capabilities approach to human rights as opposed to defining rights solely in terms of the subject’s finite and static needs which are to be mechanically met on the part of duty-bearers.

# Before I continue, I would like to explain why I am working within the Canadian context, in light of the fact that there seem to be so many more pressing cases of widespread human inequalities in the world. The short answer is because I am Canadian, and while I understand that human rights and solidarity should not be limited to a narrow nationalist application (especially in an age of globalization), I find that in my limited experience I have familiarity with the subtler problems of our society such that I can perceive their causes even better than I could the more egregious but distant problems in Africa or India, for example. Secondly, although gender inequality has widely different variants and degrees, I think that seizing on a particular, more subtle case of gender inequality in an “prosperous” nation will prove helpful in assessing blatant and involved cases of injustice when these efforts are addressed to these more urgent cases.

# The right to equal pay for work of equal value was explicitly confirmed in Section 11 of the Canadian

Human Rights Act which makes it a form of discrimination for an employer to pay men and women different wages for work of equal value. The Covenant on Economic, Social, and Cultural rights makes more specific demands - it calls for women being guaranteed conditions of work not inferior to those enjoyed by men, with equal pay for equal work; as well as “Equal opportunity for everyone to be promoted in his employment to an appropriate higher level, subject to no considerations other than those of seniority and competence.” (CITE) Much has been achieved, much remains to be achieved at the level of ensuring a fair playing-ground within the workforce.

# See particularly pages 14-21 of the report, online source retrieved 26 August 2008: <http://www.hrsdc.gc.ca/en/cs/sp/hrsdc/edd/reports/2002-002440/spah14910_e.pdf>.

# A similar point is made in the 2002 Canadian Human Resources Development report “it is increasingly recognized that treating men and women similarly will not lead to equal outcomes in many cases because of socio-economic differentials between them. The notion of "substantive equality" recognizes that both freedom from discrimination and positive actions are required to arrive at equal outcomes.”(p. 3 of the report Gender Equality in the Labour Market online source: http://www.hrsdc.gc.ca/en/cs/sp/hrsdc/edd/reports/2002-002440/spah14910_e.pdf).

# Nussbaum reflects that “feminist philosophy has frequently been skeptical of universal normative approaches” (p. 7) and carefully navigates a path between what she calls “subjective welfarism“ which treats all existing “preferences” as equal in value for political purposes, and “Platonism“ which regards the multiplicity of different preferences as being irrelevant because unreliable. In Chapter One, she is concerned with universal norms for equality and social justice. In Chapter Two, “Adaptive Preferences and Women’s Options,“ she deconstructs and reintegrates the concept of ‘preference’ in relation to justice in a political community. (Women and Human Development)

# It is among the highest in OECD countries - the 2006 rate was 58% (Stats Can: Women in Canada: Work Updates) online source: http://www.statcan.ca/english/freepub/89F0133XIE/89F0133XIE2006000.htm

# Gender Equality in the Labour Market made the following conjectures: “The barriers preventing a more extensive male involvement in parental leave remain unclear. One explanation may be that men usually earn more than their partners do, and so it makes financial sense for them to continue working. Other possible explanations may include lack of social support from friends and acquaintances; lack of exposure to non-traditional models of fathering; and unwillingness on the part of mothers to share child care responsibilities. Further research is required to determine whether financial considerations or cultural attitudes and norms explain fathers' low rates of participation in parental leave.” (p. 30 of the report) These are all likely factors - one that is not mentioned is the high-intensity investment caregiving involves as well as its relatively low socialization level - thus creating a more demanding and less rewarding option than paid occupations, with the consequence that men are reluctant to undertake it.

# One of the findings of the European Commission was that usually inquiries directed towards the situation of working mothers, while apparently motivated by a concern for child welfare, is rather “mainly due to male resistance to contributing a fair share to household and child care work.” (Wintersberger 1999: 19, as cited in Mothers as Earners, Mothers as Carers: Responsibility for Children, Social Policy, and the Tax System, p. 66 of the report. Online source at: http://www.swc-cfc.gc.ca/pubs/pubspr/0662655206/200103_0662655206_e.pdf)

# Kimmel (2000) shows that “the more that men participate in child care and the more free women are from child rearing responsibility, the higher women’s status tends to be” (53) Cited in Good for Women? Advantages and risks of a basic income from a gender perspective, p. 12, online source: http://www.epri.org.za/JulietaElgartefullpaper.pdf

# Our literature does not always distinguish between caring labour and other “domestic” labour - for the purposes of this essay we assume that “care giving” is primarily meant by references to “unpaid” or “domestic” labour in view of the fact that most housework today is related to care giving. (people are spending less time on housework and more time on child care and shopping - cf. Converging Gender Roles report)

# Stats Canada in 1998 estimated the unpaid care-giving and domestic labor of women to be worth 33% - 52% of the GDP, depending on the method used. (p. 8 of report, online source: http://www.statcan.ca/english/conferences/economic2003/hamdad3c.pdf What is also recent is a growing body of research that indicates heavy personal tolls with high-intensity caring roles (lone parenting, for example) such as poor health (Guberman, 1988; Schofield, Murphy, Nankervis, and Singh, 1997; Stephens, Franks, and Atienza, 1997 as cited in Work, Family and Community: Key Issues and Directions for Future Research: online source: http://www.rhdsc.gc.ca/en/lp/spila/wlb/wfc/10_4_2.shtml)

# “(S)tudies have suggested that fathers and mothers provide different types of care. While "there is a trend of convergence in the amount of time" mothers and fathers are involved with their children, "women continue to carry most of the responsibility dimension that involves the planning, scheduling, orchestrating and coordination of family activities" (Daly 2004, p. 12). (Converging Gender Roles: online source: http://www.statcan.ca/english/freepub/75-001-XIE/10706/art-1.htm) It seems that that much of the pressures which J.S. Mill noted in his work On the Subjection of Women remain largely relevant today (allowing for some cultural and labour-saving differences that have taken place since then).

# Haavio-Mannila, 1986; Ross, Mirowsky, and Goldstein, 1990; Revierre and Eberstein, 1992; Lennon and Rosenfield, 1992; Simon, 1995; Davies and McAlpine, 1998, as cited in Work, Family and Community (see previous footnote for citation)

# Converging Gender Roles

# Gender Equality Consultation: Assessing Gender Equality, online source at: http://www.swc-cfc.gc.ca/resources/consultations/ges09-2005/assessing_e.html. This study makes the further connection that, with an aging population, another responsibility that will increasingly challenge women is the care of elderly and disabled relatives

# Cf. Fox 1997: 144 as cited in Mothers as Earners, Mothers as Carers.

# Non-standard jobs include contract work, self-employment without employees, temporary work and part-year work or multiple jobs with a series of employers (Women in Non-Standard Jobs:The Public Policy Challenge,online source: http://www.swc-cfc.gc.ca/pubs/pubspr/0662334809/200303_0662334809_10_e.html)

# Gender Equality: Beyond the Illusion, Annex B p. 42 (available online: http://www.swc-cfc.gc.ca/resources/panel/report/report_e.pdf)

# See Poverty Issues for Canadian Women (Status of Women 2005 report) available online: http://www.swc-cfc.gc.ca/resources/consultations/ges09-2005/poverty_e.pdf

# L’Hirondelle 2004, as cited by Julieta Elgarte - Good for women? Advantages and risks of a basic income from a gender perspective, available online: http://www.epri.org.za/JulietaElgartefullpaper.pdf

# It would also be important to provide care for elderly or disabled dependents.

# For a detailed description of how a national child care program can be created and the rationale for investing in early childhood care and development, see The Atkinson Letter(2000). (Cited in Mothers as Earners)

# See above concerning the different ways in which women and men are involved in caring-related responsibilities.

# Gender Equality in the Labour Market notes the ideological impediments to achieving this goal even on the part of employees, noting that traditional ideas about the what dedication to one’s career consists of persist, and notes the influence of employers in this respect, in view of the fact that “employees are less reluctant to take advantage of flexible work policies in companies where management is amenable to alternative perspectives about the nature of work.” pp. 32-33 online source (retrieved August 26, 08): http://www.hrsdc.gc.ca/en/cs/sp/hrsdc/edd/reports/2002-002440/spah14910_e.pdf)

# Online source (retrieved August 26, 08) : http://www1.servicecanada.gc.ca/en/lp/spila/wlb/awlbc/03changing_face_canadian_workplaces.shtml

# See private studies on the advantages of job-sharing online: (both retrieved August 26, 08)<http://www.shrm.org/hrnews_published/archives/XMS_021497.asp> Also see page 5 of The New Career Paradigm: Flexibility Briefing <http://www.abcdependentcare.com/docs/ABC_NCP_Flexibility_Briefing.pdf>

Flexible work options are also increasingly talked about for their potential to address economic problems such as the necessity for downsizing (Beyond Gender, Friedan, 1997, was originally written as a response to this among other economic challenges.)

# “(A) woman with earnings is in a better position to negotiate a more equitable division of domestic labour or to have a voice in household decision-making (Hertz, 1986; Pahl, 1989; McFarlane, Beaujot and Haddad, 1998).” Cited in Work, Family, and Community, online source: http://www1.servicecanada.gc.ca/en/lp/spila/wlb/wfc/10_4_2.shtml)

# One of the most essential indicators in human prospering is one’s connections.

# Cf. Mulvale, p. 3, article Basic Income and the Canadian Welfare State: Exploring the Realms of Possibility.

# This ideological trend against the poor has been employed even at the level of the Canadian provincial government as a justification for cutting funds, as Mulvale notes. "By portraying the needy as lazy and unwilling to work, policy leaders thereby made it possible to minimize or even cut off social assistance (cf. p. )."

# Mothers as Earners notes the purely ideological basis of this typecasting of the poor that holds little or no basis in reality: “Recent international research shows that the debate about the disincentive effects of social security benefits seems to be based ‘more strongly on ideological factors than on empirical evidence’ (Forssen and Hokovirta 1991:1)’. and further notes that single mothers want to be in the workforce, most leaving social assistance by the time their children are in school. (p. 71 of the report)

# “On the one hand, women are given the message that mothers should be in the labour market. Provincial social assistance, for example, is defining lone mothers as “employable.” At the same time, public policy support is being withdrawn for many of the programs that allow women to be in the paid labour force. The consequences of this ambivalence are very serious for women, particularly for those who are economically most vulnerable.” Page 66 of the report Mothers as Earners

# Philippe Van Parijs is credited as the primary proponent of “Basic Income”; one can download his ground-breaking 2000 paper “Basic Income: A Simple and Powerful Idea for the 21st Century” from the BIEN website: http://www.basicincome.org/bien/pdf/2000VanParijs.pdf (retrieved 26 August, 2008)

# Page 17, Elgarte’s Good for Women? Advantages and risks of a basic income from a gender perspective, online source: http://www.epri.org.za/JulietaElgartefullpaper.pdf

# “Perhaps a feminist strategy for economic security for Canadian women would be more coherent, and in the long run more effective, if an unconditional and universal guarantee of adequate income for all were one of its first premises.” Mulvale, p. 19.

# There is a criticism of BI based on the fear that it would replace existing social programs. This, however, is not the form of BI which either Van Parijs or Mulvale would advocate, for example, but a system that works in conjunction with these programs.

# He states that it can be simply funded, like “all government expenditures out of a common pool of revenues from a variety of sources.” Other suggestions have been based on various taxes or a return out of shared natural resources.(CITE) http://www.basicincome.org/bien/pdf/2000VanParijs.

# “ Canadians tend to put more stock in collectivist solutions to social problems and needs, as opposed to the provision of direct benefits to individuals by a government that is relatively hands-off.” Mulvale, p. 13.

# For an example, see the focus group’s reactions in p. 12 of the document Mothers as Earners. Disinclination was expressed by some mothers for “paying for other people’s children” (p. 12) and while there was interest in the general idea that the care giving work of women should be recognized, there was generally resistance to any policies which this principle might shape (p. 13).

# Elgarte, p. 3

# Cf. Elgarte, p.4

# Cf. Mulvale, p. 17.

# (Robeyns (2001, p. 114) as cited by Mulvale,

 

Enter supporting content here